Laruelle does not exist; or, working with non-philosophy, not worshipping it

Non-Philosophy banner

By Anthony Paul Smith.

As I was thinking back on the writing of the recently published François Laruelle’s Principles of Non-Philosophy: A Critical Introduction and Guide, I kept thinking of Laruelle’s discussion of his own writing about the work of other philosophers. In an interview conducted by John Ó Maoilearca and Marjorie Gracieuse, Laruelle responded to a question regarding his method this way:

9780748645343
Laruelle & Non-Philosophy, ed. John Ó Maoilearca & Anthony Paul Smith

I have always used two philosophies at the same time. Heidegger and Nietzsche, then Derrida and Deleuze. So it is always a matter of how to eventually combine several philosophies. […]

I had the feeling that in order to completely change the concept of philosophy, two philosophies were always necessary, as if each of the philosophers represented half of philosophy, basically, which I felt to be the non-completeness of a particular philosophy; this problem would have to be resolved each time by the combination of two philosophers. I have followed this way of doing things, a little bit in spite of myself, always combining two philosophies as if each of them was lacking what the other had. You could think that this is a dialectical relation. But in fact that was not that at all, because it was, each time, two philosophies and not one philosophy and the entire history of philosophy in addition. Thus, I am part of a conjugation, I like this term a lot, of philosophies which replaced the missing concept. What was missing was the One, the One-in-One.

– From Laurelle and Non-Philosophy, ed. John Ó Maoilearca and Anthony Paul Smith

Research in the field commonly known as ‘Continental philosophy’ is often accused of the bad habit of trend chasing. The popularity of one figures wanes as a new industry of commentary waxes. Of course, this criticism is largely unfair to the work of many philosophers and researchers in philosophy. Texts like the recent Bloomsbury Companion to Continental Philosophy (formally Continuum Companion to Continental Philosophy), edited by Beth Lord and John Ó Maoilearca, highlight the thematics and questions that drive the various research paradigms within Continental philosophy.

There is still something that the critics are right to caution us against. Undoubtedly, those of us trained in the traditions of European philosophy from phenomenology to Marxism are tempted to become acolytes of the persons in our use of archives and figures that act as indexes. But there is still a real power and possibility in this use of an archive, an index or a tradition. While perhaps the critics of Continental philosophy are clear sighted regarding the inevitable inherent pitfalls of this approach, attention is rarely given to the fundamentally communitarian tradition here. This tradition has, at its best, been better connected to the lived reality of the cultures, language and everydayness these philosophical works emerged from. This is even true when these philosophical works are critical of that culture and, I would hazard, especially so.

The most insightful and inventive thinkers in any tradition recognise the ultimately false nature of these boundaries. This includes philosophical ones even when they would rather not recognise themselves as relative and contingent communities of tradition. The most interesting thinkers simply go where thought is at play, including outside the boundaries of the academic guild of philosophy.

When I first encountered the work of Laruelle, he struck me as just such a figure.

Laruelle
François Laruelle at the Miguel Abreu Gallery, NYC, 6 April 2011

François Laruelle, at the Miguel Abreu Gallery, New York City on April 6, 2011

My undergraduate training in philosophy was precisely in the methods of Continental philosophy. I was taught to think through the history of thought, through the works of others, to study the archive and to deploy it in new ways. I was taught to translate thought from one domain to another, to take what was useful and well tested in method from here and there, in order to try and do something worth the name of philosophy. At least worth what we intend as the most beautiful about that name.

For my earlier apprenticeship the most important philosophical figures were Derrida and Deleuze. Their work diverges a great deal, of course, but they both worked through the history of philosophy to answer questions that were bigger than that history. At the same time the answer they gave differed, even on the question of difference itself. A difference regarding difference that we might index with reference to the figures of transcendence and immanence respectively. I struggled to find a method that allowed me to engage with both of them, to make use of both of them, that didn’t try to hastily cover over their differences. More than that, I wanted to find a more explicit development of their implicit method of working through the history of philosophy. Derrida’s deconstruction, of course, offers its own rules but this was another example of divergence in their philosophy as such rules seemed at odds with Deleuze’s more constructivist method.

9780748685271

Laruelle had worked through this problem of the way Derrida and Deleuze differ and create a complete philosophy already in 1986 in his Philosophies of Difference (translated in 2010 by Rocco Gangle, author of his own critical introduction and guide to that text). His project of non-philosophy is a great many things but what first attracted me to study the project was the attentive and consistent way he treated philosophy and the names that populate it as simple materials for the project of thinking. With Principles of Non-Philosophy, Laruelle elaborates on the concepts and methods of non-philosophy with even greater attention. Yet he carries out this elaboration without much mention or textual analysis of the history of philosophy one sees in Philosophies of Difference. This is in part because Principles of Non-Philosophy aims to elaborate the very project it is detailing without any distance between that elaboration and the project itself. It is wildly constructivist and undeniably rooted in the history of the European philosophical tradition.

So when I was asked to write a guide to Principles of Non-Philosophy I wanted to do so in the spirit of non-philosophy. I did not want to write a text that pretended to be the definitive reading of Laruelle’s text. Instead I wanted to offer readers a kind of constellation guide so that they could plot their own course using his method for their own projects. I wanted to write a guide whose aim was not to elevate yet another figure for the commentary industry, a new trend to chase, but to help those who have been so long harassed by philosophy to find tools to disempower it and use it for their own work. Towards that end I focused on elaborating the history and concepts behind major concepts and methodological themes in Principles as well as my own glosses on those concepts.

At one point in the interview quoted from earlier, Laruelle responds to a question regarding his authority and ownership of non-philosophy with this remark:

Laruelle does not exist.

While of course he deserves the credit for his work, Laruelle is speaking here in a way that collapses the distance between explaining non-philosophy and practising it. There is to be no guru in non-philosophy, no new figure to genuflect before, though this is not an excuse to simply run roughshod over that work with poor readings. Instead it is an invitation to build with that work, to take it in new directions unforeseen by the one who developed the method used. It is in that spirit that I hope this guide is useful to those who wish to work with it.


Anthony Paul Smith Anthony Paul Smith is Assistant Professor in Religion at La Salle University. He is also the author of Laruelle: A Stranger Thought (Polity, May 2016). He is the translator of Future Christ: A Lesson in Heresy (Bloomsbury, 2010) and co-translator of Principles of Non-Philosophy (Bloomsbury, 2013), both by François Laruelle, and co-editor of After the Postsecular and the Postmodern: New Essays in Continental Philosophy of Religion.

Anthony Paul Smith’s books with Edinburgh University Press:

You might also like:

eupjournalsblog
eupjournalsblog
Articles: 162

5 Comments

  1. Smith gives a good account of the dream of non-philosophy, a dream that existed and guided the steps of many long before Laruelle came to propose a new embodiment for it. This dream is not universal, to claim as much would be a philosophical move that many, including Laruelle, would prefer not to make. Rather than universal, the dream is “generic”, to use one of Laruelle’s non-philosophical terms. Many people are passionate about philosophy (philosophical concepts, theories, arguments, and examples), but do not want to be caught in the confines of philosophy as domain or discipline or guild, nor do they want to be excluded from it. They do not want the tyranny of experts but the democracy of thought.

    These dreamers, whatever their profession or situation in life, are ordinary people who have encountered philosophy in some way and glimpsed something of interest and concern for their everyday living. Enthusiastic at first, often they have felt disappointed and become a little wary, but still they continue to hope and to search, to try out and experiment with philosophy, without stopping at the boundaries. These people form a community outside the academic guilds and grids, and they share a common dream, that thought be democratic and unbounded.

    Non-philosophy is one embodiment of that dream and that practice, it is one possible codification. Laruelle does well to declare “Laruelle does not exist”. There is a Buddhist ring to it, as if he were declaring “Laruelle does not exist, and neither do you!”. We should not be misled by Laruelle’s own obsessive circling around (and perhaps inside?) Christianity, for example in his books THE FUTURE CHRIST, NON-PHILOSOPHICAL MYSTICISM, and CHRISTO-FICTION. Just as the Buddha refused to answer the big philosophical questions, saying “The Buddha does not exist, work out your salvation with diligence”, we can hear Laruelle as saying “Laruelle and non-philosophy do not exist, work out your non-philosophy with diligence”. Not existing (should we call it, in a new sense of the prefix non-, “non-existence”?) implies hard work and rigour over a very long time.

    Laruelle is no messiah, no prophet, no guru. He comes from, and belongs to, the great community of dreamers and practitioners of philosophy unbound. He cannot lord it over us, and has no desire to (most of the time!). He can contribute something of worth to be examined and, perhaps, used by us or inspire us to emulation. French philosophers are passionate readers and Laruelle has read widely and deeply in philosophy. Far from calling on us to “forget” Foucault (Deleuze, Derrida, Lyotard, Badiou, Althusser, Lacan, etc.), he inspires us to read them with intensity and freedom. And he invites us to read his works, and to write our own, in the same intense and free manner. Along with the erudition and the rigour, there is great freedom in Laruelle’s texts.

    Laruelle is not a guru, he is one of us. In a democracy, we are entitled to ask: what have you done with all that time devoted to reading and thinking about philosophy? What do you have to contribute to the community? Not in the sense of judgement and critique, but of evaluating a contribution from a fellow dreamer, and a fellow traveler. Many of us have read the same books over the years, have had many of the same influences. Amongst the living, in France, we can cite Alain Badiou, Bruno Latour, Bernard Stiegler, Michel Serres.

    All of these thinkers share with Laruelle a desire for a democracy of thought. All are pluralists, concerned about the contradictory mix of tolerant relativism of opinion and brutal realism of exploitation that characterises our society, and its relation to others. Democracy means being open to others, and also open to change. These thinkers also emphasise that time and change run as deep as anything. Nothing final can be said, and the real is ultimately ineffable, as it cannot be reduced to any of our particular working realities.

    I do not think that contemporary philosophy in France is “post-Continental”, only some noisy and conceited newcomers pretend to that. All that is living and worthwhile in that passionate community contributes to a thought that is pluralist, valuing change, humble and non-dogmatic in what can be said about the real, open to experience and experiment, and above all democratic. Laruelle’s thought is a welcome contribution to this community, and much can be learned from it if it is approached with fellow feeling.

  2. A problem arises in translating some of Laruelle’s terminology. He talks about the “principe de la philosophie suffisante” (translated as the “principle of sufficient philosophy”) or the “principe de la suffisance philosophique” (the “principle of philosophical sufficiency). There is an ambiguity here as in French “suffisance” means both “sufficiency” and “arrogance”. This is why I propose the translation “complacent completeness”.

    There is no shame in being passionate about a particular philosopher and being influenced by their ideas to the point of working in their wake.

    It all depends on whether you are fixated on an identity or to something else in the philosophers you are devoted to. Badiou tells us that our fidelities constitute us as subjects, but fidelity is not to an ego nor to a more or less expert knowledge (finite constituted identities), but to working out the consequences of “truths” (infinite de-constituted generic potencies). Badiou does not consider philosophy to be a truth procedure, but the lesson is the same.

    The epithet “Deleuzian” is the name of a finite covering over an infinite generic process, but so is “Lacanian” or “Badiousian”. That means the image of thought as knowledge and of the subject as subjugated identity. Or such an epithet can name a fidelity to the Truths as open non-totalised multiplicitous infinite processes inscribed in and passing through a work. You identify with one, you incorporate in the other.

    Too often we conflate “philosopher” with “philosophy teacher” school teacher, lecturer, professor). Philosophy teacher is the name of a particular job in the capitalist economy. It is a finite identity that very often covers over the infinite processes involved and deployed in philosophy. “Analyst” too, even “Lacanian analyst”, names a job, office hours, fees and taxes, institutional training, etc.

    Laruelle would tell us that there is too much “sufficiency”, too much complacent completeness, in these identities.

Leave a Reply

Your email address will not be published. Required fields are marked *